Philip Larkin was once asked whether, living in Hull rather than within the ambit of literary London, he ever felt too removed from the centre of things. āOh no,ā he replied. āI very much feel the need to be on the periphery of things.ā Missing out was, for Larkin, an essential part of the creative life. While other writers record the overwhelming intensity of felt experience, his poems tend to dwell on the careers he isnāt pursuing, the money he hasnāt accumulated, and ā in his ode āTo My Wifeā ā the people he has chosen not to spend his life with. When the same interviewer asked, āDo you feel you could have had a much happier life?ā the answer came back: āNot without being someone else.ā
That line doesnāt feature in Andrew H Millerās new work of literary criticism, On Not Being Someone Else: Tales of Our Unled Lives, though āTo My Wifeā is quoted in full, as is āI Remember, I Rememberā, a detailed reminiscence of all the things Larkin didnāt get up to in his childhood. Larkinās most ruthlessly unsentimental poem on this subject, however, is āDockery and Sonā, which meditates on the difference between one life path and another before concluding that, actually, it doesnāt really matter, because our choices are determined by deep-lying psychological habits and in any case weāll all be dead before long:
Life is first boredom, then fear.
Whether or not we use it, it goes,
And leaves what something hidden from us chose,
And age, and then the only end of age.
Faced with Larkinās nihilism, Miller politely suggests that it maybe isnāt the whole picture. While Larkin writes as though āweāre defined by loss,ā Miller tells us, āIād like to think that something is sometimes gained.ā He also manages to look on the bright side of Virginia Woolf, concentrating on the āhappy, even deliciousā moments in her prose rather than the intimations of mental illness and despair. Although the book, very sensibly, does not try to live up to its self-help-y jacket blurb ā āOn Not Being Someone Else offers the balm that when we confront our imaginary selves, we discover who we areā ā it is written in a gently soothing tone, and for the most part Miller finds poets and novelists to be consoling, helpful company rather than stunningly original or dazzlingly subversive.
The preface to this concise and thoughtful book is a study in self-deprecation: Miller warns us that he doesnāt āreally argue for many thesesā, he just wants to point out a distinctive theme of modern literature: the exploration of the road not taken ā to cite the most famous example, and perhaps the best-known American poem of the 20th century. It is, Miller persuasively argues, a constant preoccupation of the last 200 years, from David Copperfieldās disappointed brooding to the acronyms which have recently entered the language. āAh ā YOLO plus FOMO,ā says one of Millerās colleagues when told about the book.
But Miller has another argument to make, and an ambitious one: that contemplating the lives we didnāt lead can help us āto find meaningā. Or at least, help us feel that way: poems and stories, he writes, ācreate with special power the experience of verging on meaning: something important is being said, but what isnāt clear.ā
Join the discussion
Join like minded readers that support our journalism by becoming a paid subscriber
To join the discussion in the comments, become a paid subscriber.
Join like minded readers that support our journalism, read unlimited articles and enjoy other subscriber-only benefits.
SubscribePhilip Larkin also said, possibly in a letter to a girlfriend, that the personality was not self-chosen; that to have done differently, he would have had to have thought differently, to have thought differently, he would have had to have felt differently and to have felt differently, he would have had to be someone else.
As your fellow UH columnist, John Gray, has been saying for years, we have far less autonomy than we think we have.
Well put… which is why, in the end, I think we have to accept, rather than trying to deny or dispute, the sanctity and specificity of individual experience. Each of us is who he is.
An interesting, nuanced and gentle article. But I think an important point is being missed. Of course literature can’t supply transcendent meaning. Of course it can’t dictate morality. But I think the great poems, plays and, especially, novels (one may add the great films too – all the narrative arts) are our most comprehensive source of applied ethics – they offer a record of imagined moral choices made in specific defined situations which can help us to clarify the particular implications and consequences of whatever ethical foundation (which will necessarily be generalised) we have. For instance, consider Dorothea Brooke’s situation in Middlemarch, when she is asked to make a promise by her husband, fully intends to make a promise, and would have made that promise, had it not been for the fact that her husband dies before she can do so. Here, the reader has to think very carefully about what a promise is, what it means, what kind of promises are reasonable and unreasonable to make and to demand, and to what extent we should consider ourselves bound by them.
That kind of crux offers, I really think, the sort of scope for pondering that makes literature particularly valuable – it allows us to ask, in a controlled, reflective way, what the particular consequences of particular moral positions may be in particular situations. That’s a habit of mind which we should all strive to cultivate.
I’ve experienced transcendence many times when deeply immersed in a work of art. Theatre has been particularly powerful for me — when a large group of people go beyond their individual selves together, the potential for something very rich emerges. A well-told story is an opportunity to become someone else for a time and develop empathy. You need concentration though — it won’t work if you’ve got one eye on your phone.
Even ordinary, everyday moments can be a gateway to an expansive experience. I’ve found meditation a great help with this, though it does take time and practice.
“Experiencing transcendence” is rather different from “transcendent meaning”, though. I guess it’s the difference between looking at the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel and being awed by Michaelangelo’s genius, the beauty of the images, the coherence of the scheme, the persuasive expression of an ideology on the one hand (those are all examples of “experiencing transcendence”), and on the other, looking at the Sistine Chapel and actually believing that it is a representation of the verities of Christianity – that would be art imbued with “transcendent meaning”.
Would who want to be someone else?
It’s a Wonderful Life is a knowing reworking of A Christmas Carol. Dickens may have been criticising the predestination of puritanism. He had not long returned from the USA and had criticised what he saw (facilely rather) as the rapaciousness and hypocrisy of puritanism, thus anticipating Weber’s thesis “Capitalism and the Protestant Ethic”. Hence the equal emphasis – again slightly clunky – by Dickens (along with a direct relationship with Christ – “Are you the spirit whose coming was foretold to me?” ” I am.”) on enjoyment and charity and the possibility of change.
It’s a Wonderful Life is also implicitly anti-Puritan and pro-Catholic (its director, Frank Capra, was Italian-born, and the Italian Martini is one of the most sympathetic minor characters).
Thanks. I do think Dickens’ attack on puritanism as the hypocritical basis of capitalism was unfair. I believe Weber’s thesis has also come in for criticism.
Am not clever enough to understand free-will/determinism, etc. We may inevitably be “determined” by the past, the entire past including our consciousness, which makes the future unpredictable, and this gives us a seeming-moment of free-will in the present (intuitive leap!!). We don’t like being “determined” by other people though! This is what we mean by “liberty”, but we don’t like loneliness or anarchy either…
It’s more of an inversion than a reworking, Bailey being the anti-Scrooge.
I suppose the interesting thing then is this “Dickensian” (he did not pretend to be a philosopher!) view of “capitalism” as a consequence of a complete lack of free-will and the “liberal” idea of it.